The ecological systems theory of development states that only genetic factors are worth studying.

  • Journal List
  • Behav Anal
  • v.39(2); 2016 Oct
  • PMC6701262

Behav Anal. 2016 Oct; 39(2): 243–258.

Abstract

The developmental systems approach is a perspective that has been adopted by increasing numbers of developmental scientists since it emerged in the twentieth century. The overview presented in this paper makes clear that proponents of this approach and proponents of modern behavior analysis should be natural allies. Despite some distinctions between the two schools of thought, the essential ideas associated with each are compatible with the other; in particular, scientists in both camps work to analyze the provenance of behavior and recognize the central role that contextual factors play in behavioral expression.

Keywords: Developmental systems, Nature-nurture, Phylogeny fallacy, Instincts

In the second half of the twentieth century, a new approach to the analysis of behavior began to emerge in the scientific and philosophical literatures, an approach that emphasized both the developmental history of an organism and the complex relations that give rise to organisms’ behavioral and biological traits (Ford & Lerner, 1992; Gottlieb, 1991a, 1992; Johnston, 1987; Lickliter & Berry, 1990; Oyama, 1985; West & King, 1987). Emerging from work in developmental psychology (Thelen & Smith, 1994), philosophy of science (Griffiths & Gray, 1994), developmental biology (Gilbert, 1992; Nijhout, 1990), and interdisciplinary fields related to these subjects (Michel & Moore, 1995), this approach grew out of ideas that had been advanced in earlier decades (e.g., by Kuo, 1967; Lehrman, 1953; Schneirla, 1957) and was initially called “Developmental Systems Theory;” it has sometimes been known by its acronym, DST (Ford & Lerner, 1992; Griffiths & Gray, 1994; Griffiths & Tabery, 2013; Johnston, 2010; Johnston & Lickliter, 2009; Oyama, Griffiths, & Gray 2001). By the early 1990s, researchers interested in behavior analysis were already attending actively to the growing DST literature (Midgley & Morris, 1992; Morris, Lazo, & Smith 2004; Schneider, 2003, 2007).

Before proceeding, it is important to be clear about what the acronym DST refers to. Keller (2005) has distinguished at least three different ways in which DST has been used in the past 20 years (see also Pradeu, 2010). In particular, she noted that while Ford and Lerner’s (1992) book on DST focused on the importance of temporal dynamics in the development of an individual organism’s behavior, Griffiths and Gray’s (1994) treatment of DST focused on the important roles of non-genetic factors in the evolution of behavioral and biological phenotypes. Thus, Keller identified an important difference between two schools of thought, both of which used the same acronym: “Where one version of developmental systems theory [Griffiths and Gray’s] emphasizes the multiplicity of resources employed in heredity, development, and evolution, the other [Ford and Lerner’s] emphasizes the critical importance of temporal dynamics in the dialectics of individual development” (p. 412). To make matters more confusing, another closely related literature used DST to refer to dynamic (rather than “developmental”) systems theory (Thelen & Smith, 1994), an approach that explored the development of human behavior using the mathematics of nonlinear systems, which had been pioneered by theorists who were attempting to explain the emergent behavior of self-organizing systems like stars, hurricanes, and ecosystems (Kelso, 2000; Stewart, 1989). Regardless of these differences, all versions of DST appear to share some central ideas (Keller, 2005).

One of the essential ideas shared by the various forms of DST is that all phenotypes—including both biological and behavioral traits—emerge spontaneously from the mechanical interactions of a large number of factors that together constitute a single complex system (Griffiths & Gray, 1994; Noble, 2006; Pradeu, 2015; Thelen & Smith, 1994). Such a system normally comprises influential factors such as DNA, cytoplasm and its contents, cell membranes and their embedded proteins, hormones, neurotransmitters, other organ systems, other individual organisms, societal factors, and physical features of the environment. In addition, at any given moment, a system’s components are as they are in part because of historical factors, including the system’s own behavioral history. Importantly, the emergent products of these mechanical interactions are novel, in the sense of being qualitatively distinct from the system components that give rise to them; accordingly, phenotypes cannot be reduced to any of the components at lower levels of the system (Witherington & Lickliter, 2016) and they are not contained in any way in any of these lower-order components (Johnston & Gottlieb, 1990; Johnston & Lickliter, 2009).

Therefore, this “systems view” carries with it a second essential idea: genes cannot be considered the primary determinants of any phenotype (Griffiths & Tabery, 2013; Lickliter, 2013; Oyama 1985/2000) because contextual factors always play indispensable, informational roles in phenotype development (Griffiths & Gray, 1994; Thelen & Smith, 1994). In fact, DST proponents have concluded that genes are no more foundational than any of the other system components that contribute to phenotype development (for a detailed exploration of this point, see Moore, 2002). Given these essential ideas, all forms of DST recognize development as epigenetic (discussed below) and probabilistic rather than predetermined (Godfrey-Smith, 2001; Gottlieb, 1991a, 1992, 1998, 2007; Pradeu, 2010); predetermination is impossible in such systems in part because the contextual factors that contribute to development are, themselves, not invariably predictable. And because organisms are responsive to contexts that have the features they do in part because of those very organisms’ behaviors (Lewontin, 2000), all forms of DST reject as inherently flawed the traditional view that nature and nurture can contribute in independent ways to development (Lewkowicz, 2011; Overton, 2006; Stotz, 2012). Developmental systems theorists in psychology, philosophy, and biology have focused on different kinds of phenomena or have advocated the use of different kinds of methods, but they all share these overarching perspectives on the developmental origins of behaviors and other biological phenotypes. In addition, like behavior analysts, these theorists are all committed to elucidating the mechanisms through which phenotypes arise, because such an approach promises to yield interventions with the potential to improve the human condition (Moore, 2009, 2015a, 2015b).

As the worldview shared by these theorists is better thought of as a perspective than a formal theory, a number of writers (e.g., Lickliter, 2013; Moore, 2002; Spencer, Blumberg, McMurray, Robinson, Samuelson, & Tomblin 2009) have begun referring to this collection of ideas as the developmental systems (DS) approach, rather than as DST. I will be using this terminology henceforth in this paper.

The DS Perspective on Nature and Nurture

By explicitly rejecting the traditional nature-nurture dichotomy, the DS approach forces a reconsideration of earlier ways of thinking about behavior. One important consequence of adopting the DS perspective is the need to relinquish the older idea that behaviors can be categorized as having roots in either phylogeny or ontogeny. This idea, which was a conventional viewpoint through much of the twentieth century, held that some behaviors reflect learning that occurs during an individual’s lifetime (i.e., nurture) whereas other behaviors reflect evolutionary processes (i.e., nature). This viewpoint supported a sharp distinction between species-typical behaviors that appear unlearned—so-called instincts—and other behaviors that emerge following specific experiences, such as classical or operant conditioning. Because unlearned, species-typical behaviors were understood to require explanations in terms of natural selection operating on an evolutionary timescale—and because the modern evolutionary synthesis of biology held that evolution results only from changes in the frequencies of genes in a population (Gottlieb, 1992; Wereha & Racine, 2012)—such “instinctive” behaviors were effectively regarded by many writers as genetically determined. However, because DS theorists understand all phenotypes to emerge from numerous interactions among components that constitute a single, complex, integrated system, they argue that there are no behaviors that can be attributed directly and exclusively to genes. In fact, molecular biologists have known for some time that DNA cannot single-handedly specify behaviors (more on this below). Therefore, no behaviors can be dismissed as instinctive (in the sense of “genetically determined”); instead, behaviors that seem instinctive—just like behaviors observed after operant or classical conditioning—require analysis to discover the factors and mechanisms that give rise to them.1

In a seminal 1990 article, Lickliter and Berry explicated this argument by identifying a misconception they called “The Phylogeny Fallacy.” This fallacy holds that there are two different causes of phenotypes: proximate (developmental or ontogenetic) and ultimate (evolutionary or phylogenetic). In rejecting this fallacy, DS proponents hold that when it comes to analyzing the origins of a behavior, no principled distinction can be made between “inherited” and “acquired” behaviors, because all behaviors emerge in real time from the same kinds of interactions, interactions that occur between components of developing systems. As most twentieth-century scientists saw things, “innate” or “unlearned” behaviors could be accounted for by phylogenetic contingencies, whereas “acquired” or “learned” behaviors could not; but according to Lickliter and Berry, this conceptualization accepts a false dichotomy. And one unfortunate effect of uncritically accepting this false dichotomy is an openness to the idea that events that occurred prior to the conception of an organism can be responsible for that organism’s later behaviors, as if behaviors can somehow emerge in real time without any proximate causes being responsible for their emergence. Although events in the distant past can contribute to behaviors in real time via their influences on the state of some of the components comprising a developing system, the behaviors themselves are always influenced by proximate factors, regardless of whether those behaviors are learned or unlearned.

Prior to the ascendance of DS thinking in some branches of the behavioral sciences, it was generally assumed that nature and nurture could be disentangled using particular methodological approaches. One of these approaches controls for genetic factors, either by studying research participants who are monozygotic twins or by using subjects that come from isogenic, inbred strains of laboratory animals. Another of these approaches attempts to control for experiential factors, either by studying newborn research participants, or by using animals raised in controlled environments; the idea here is to study organisms that either have had no experiences at all with certain classes of stimuli, or have had nearly identical upbringings. As explained in the next section, DS proponents have rejected both of these approaches as being unable to disentangle phylogenetic and ontogenetic contributions to behavior. In fact, these theorists have concluded that it is not possible in principle to untangle these contributions to behavior.

Insights from Developmental Science

As far back as the mid-1950s, scientists such as Lehrman (1953), Schneirla (1957), and Kuo (1967) had argued that a truly developmental approach to the study of behavioral phenotypes would always reveal proximate causes of behavior; in contrast, viewing so-called instinctive behaviors as “immanent, preformed, [or] inherited” (Lehrman, 1953, p. 359) would be a mistake, because doing so would interfere with genuine analysis of the development of those behaviors. From the perspective of developmental science, the question of interest is how a behavior emerges, regardless of whether that behavior is species-typical and seemingly unlearned, or idiosyncratic and obviously influenced by the organism’s past experiences. That is, all complex behaviors must be understood to emerge from developmental processes, and it is the job of the developmental scientist to explore these processes.

This insight illuminates a problem with research methods designed to identify “instincts” by studying newborn animals, or animals raised in highly controlled environments. The classic example of such a method is the so-called isolation experiment, in which the behaviors of animals are deemed instinctive if those behaviors emerge even when opportunities to learn them seem to have been eliminated. Most mid-century behavioral scientists considered such behaviors to be inherited. However, developmentalists like Lehrman argued strenuously that we cannot know prior to developmental analysis what the relevant antecedent experiences are for the development of a behavior, so it is never appropriate to assume that such proximate causes do not exist (i.e., that the behavior has merely been inherited via some unspecified mechanism). Instead, proponents of the DS approach recognize that factors present at one point in time are themselves the products of earlier developmental events (Griffiths & Tabery, 2013), so developmental analysis always requires a search for antecedent factors as well as experimental elucidation of how those factors interact mechanistically.

In part to demonstrate the importance of the developmental approach, Gottlieb (1991b, 1997) sought to discover the proximate causes underlying the consistent preference that newborn Mallard ducklings exhibit for their mothers’ species-typical assembly calls. Even when duck embyros (in eggs) are raised in incubators where they are prevented from hearing maternal vocalizations and from hearing the vocalizations of nearby siblings, the ducklings still hatch already exhibiting a preference for the maternal call. At first glance, this seems like a behavior that has been inherited. However, Gottlieb’s (1991b) research revealed that experiences with the embryos’ own vocalizations—vocalizations that, to the human ear, do not sound at all like the maternal assembly call (Gottlieb, 1991a)—are essential in the development of the newborns’ preferences. Thus, an experiential factor is crucial in the development of the behavioral preference, even though the behavior certainly appears (at first glance) to develop independently of experience (because it emerges even in animals whose sensory experience has been severely limited).

This finding lends credence to an understanding Lehrman highlighted in 1953: “The isolation experiment [in which an animal is deprived of normal experiences] … provides at best a negative indication that certain specified environmental factors probably are not directly involved in the genesis of a particular behavior. However, the isolation experiment by its very nature does not give a positive indication that behavior is ‘innate’ or indeed any information at all about … [the] development of the behavior …” (1953, p. 343). Studies other than Gottlieb’s have likewise revealed that experiences that are not obviously related to specific behaviors can nonetheless be crucial antecedents of those behaviors (Alberts & Ronca, 2012; Goldstein, King, & West 2003; Wallman, 1979). To provide a single example from a primate species, Masataka (1993) found that squirrel monkeys can learn to fear snakes as a result not of exposure to snakes (or other snake-like stimuli), but as a result of exposure to organisms like grasshoppers or crickets that have been placed in their food! And although studies involving newborn organisms might seem useful when trying to make a point about unlearned behaviors, the fact remains that newborn animals have many sorts of prenatal experiences that influence their postnatal behaviors (e.g., see Alberts & Ronca, 2012). To provide a single example, human fetuses hear their mothers’ voices, an experience that influences some of their auditory preferences shortly after birth (DeCasper & Fifer, 1980; DeCasper & Spence, 1986). Similarly, animals raised in controlled environments have some experiences that likely influence their subsequent behaviors. A DS approach encourages investigations of the development of such behaviors by insisting that researchers continue to seek the proximate causes of those behaviors rather than simply declaring behaviors without obvious experiential causes to have been inherited or somehow shaped by “phylogenetic contingencies.”

Of course, some of our behaviors reflect specific experiences whereas others seem only to reflect the basic structures of our bodies (e.g., swallowing, waste elimination, etc.). But as proponents of the DS approach see it, such a distinction masks critical similarities in the development of all of our behaviors. In fact, while the species-typical structures of our bodies might seem to be genetically determined, this illusion fades once we begin to study the emergence of these structures in development. Behaviors that reflect the basic structures of our bodies—no less than behaviors that obviously reflect our experiences—must still be subjected to developmental analysis if we hope to understand them. The precise point DS proponents seek to make is that it is conceptually problematic to draw sharp distinctions between behaviors that obviously reflect experiences and behaviors that appear to emerge independently of experiences, because all phenotypes depend on both genetic and non-genetic factors for their development. Conceptualizations that permit different modes of explanation for learned versus unlearned behaviors risk underestimating both the extent to which non-genetic factors contribute to bodily structures and functions and the extent to which genetic factors contribute to learned behaviors. Thus, from the perspective of the DS approach, we should never consider any behaviors to be inherited and exempt from further developmental analysis (Blumberg, 2005).

Just as they have questioned the value of isolation experiments, proponents of the DS approach have also rejected the idea, advanced by the authors of thousands of papers (see Plomin, DeFries, McClearn, & McGuffin 2008), that studies of identical and fraternal twins can reveal something about developmental versus evolutionary contributions to human behaviors. Francis Galton (1907) was the first to recommend the use of these sorts of studies as a way to tease apart nature and nurture, and the method continues to be implemented in the twenty-first century mostly as Galton originally envisioned it. Unfortunately, although monozygotic twins could, in theory, allow researchers to effectively control for genetic factors, there is little reason to believe that twin studies are capable of providing useful answers to questions about how evolutionary versus developmental processes contribute to phenotypes. A formal critique of twin studies is beyond the scope of this paper, but such critiques are available in numerous other locations (Burt & Simons, 2014; Chaufan & Joseph, 2013; Joseph, 2015; Moore, 2002, 2006, 2008, 2013a, 2013b; Moore & Shenk, 2016; Richardson & Norgate 2005; Shultziner, 2013a, 2013b), and these critiques have identified a variety of problems with twin studies, problems that render these methods unhelpful in studying phenotype origins.

Although twin study methods are among the most powerful tools available to quantitative behavioral geneticists (i.e., the researchers who took up Galton’s goal of disentangling nature and nurture), they are not satisfactory tools for studying phenotype development because they do not actually explore biological processes. In fact, in their authoritative textbook, Behavioral genetics, Plomin and colleagues (2008) noted that “quantitative genetics, such as twin and adoption studies, depends on Mendel’s laws of heredity but does not require knowledge of the biological basis of heredity” (p. 40). Because twin studies ignore the biological and behavioral processes that produce phenotypes, they are not equipped to answer developmental questions about the proximate causes of those phenotypes (behavioral or otherwise). Instead, as the DS approach insists (Griffiths & Tabery, 2008, 2013; Tabery, 2014), a thorough understanding of such causes requires knowledge about how it is that biological entities like DNA segments, micro-RNAs, proteins, and cell membranes physically interact with their contexts to construct nervous systems that generate behaviors in context-dependent ways (where “context” must be understood to include both an organism’s current circumstances and its historical experiences). Understanding something about how biological processes build the nervous systems that contribute to behavior is essential if one is to have a comprehensive understanding of behavior.

The basic facts of biology indicate that DNA is used in context-dependent ways during development to help produce RNA (Griffiths & Stotz, 2006; Lewontin, 2000; Moore, 2002, 2013a; Stotz, 2006). This is all DNA can do; it cannot single-handedly cause nervous systems to have their characteristics, let alone cause full-blown behaviors. In fact, as one early advocate of the DS approach pointed out, there is always “a long and tortuous developmental route” between complex phenotypes like behavior and the molecules that DNA helps to construct (Johnston, 1987, p. 160). Therefore, regardless of what twin studies might tell us about the heritability of a behavior, that behavior emerges from multiple developmental processes involving more than DNA alone (Moore, 2002); even if a behavioral characteristic were found to be 100 % heritable, a developmental analysis would still uncover non-genetic factors that contribute to the emergence of the behavior, factors that are informative and constructive regarding development, even though they are not genetic factors (Griffiths & Tabery, 2013; Lickliter & Berry, 1990; Lickliter & Honeycutt, 2015; Michel & Moore, 1995; Moore, 2006, 2013a, 2013b; Moore & Shenk, 2016). The fact that DNA cannot determine precise phenotypes independently of non-genetic factors is evident from the behavioral, physiological, and morphological differences that can be observed between identical twins or between cloned animals.

Behavioral Epigenetics: Molecular Biology’s Confirmation of the DS Approach

Although the DS approach dates to the 1980s or earlier, remarkable progress began to be made in the very late 1990s in a branch of molecular biology known as epigenetics, and the developments in this field have strongly reinforced the message espoused by proponents of the DS approach. Epigenetics is a research field that explores gene expression, that is, what it is that leads specific segments of DNA (i.e., genes) in specific cells to be transcribed into segments of RNA in specific spatial and temporal contexts. A sub-field of epigenetics, known as behavioral epigenetics (Lester et al., 2011; Van IJzendoorn, Bakermans-Kranenburg, & Ebstein 2011), is concerned specifically with how psychological processes—such as emotional reactivity, behavior, and memory—affect and are affected by gene expression (Moore, 2015b). Studies of behavioral epigenetics have confirmed that in contrast to the traditional view of genes as capable of actively influencing phenotype development, DNA is actually better thought of as reactive to its context (Gilbert & Sarkar, 2000; Keller, 2014); as Pradeu has written, “genes in the organism are not so much activators as they are activated” (2015, p. 11). Thus, as developmental scientists have been asserting for decades, DNA should be understood to be sensitive to its context and only one of several factors in a complex, integrated system that gives rise to biological and behavioral phenotypes.

Among the best-known studies on behavioral epigenetics are those conducted in the labs of Meaney and Szyf (Meaney, 2010; Meaney & Szyf, 2005; Weaver et al., 2004; Weaver, Meaney, & Szyf 2006). This work explored why rat pups that are licked and groomed frequently by their mothers in the first 10 days after birth grow up to be adults that are less reactive in stressful situations than are rats that were licked and groomed less frequently as pups. An extensive program of research ultimately revealed that the experience of being licked and groomed early in life led to the activation of a DNA segment in hippocampal cells that is required for the production of a stress-moderating protein, the glucocorticoid receptor. In the absence of this sort of early life maternal caregiving, rats grew up with a deactivated segment of DNA at this location, and consequently wound up with fewer glucocorticoid receptors in their brains and increased stress reactivity in adulthood.

The finding that a maternal behavior can epigenetically activate a DNA segment confirmed the DS insight that experiential factors can alter the functioning of an organism’s genetic endowment. This discovery suggests that starting at conception, nature and nurture can participate in a real-time “dialogue” that gives rise to phenotypes; this arrangement means that phenotypic outcomes can be influenced by either experiential or molecular variables (Szyf & Bick, 2013; Zhang & Meaney, 2010). Several kinds of experiences have now been found to influence the activity of a variety of DNA segments in a variety of cell types in a variety of animal species. For example, exercise (Gomez-Pinilla, Zhuang, Feng, Ying, & Fan 2011), poverty (Borghol et al., 2012), substance addiction (Maze & Nestler, 2011), or social isolation (Cole, Hawkley, Arevalo, Sung, Rose, & Cacioppo 2007) can all affect the expression of DNA; specific experiences are associated with the activation or deactivation of DNA used to construct arginine vasopressin (Murgatroyd et al., 2009), brain-derived neurotrophic factor (Roth, Lubin, Funk, & Sweatt 2009), or the serotonin transporter promoter (Devlin, Brain, Austin, & Oberlander 2010); cells in the liver (Lillycrop, Phillips, Jackson, Hanson, & Burdge 2005), blood (e.g., T cells), and prefrontal cortex (Provençal et al., 2012) contain DNA that can be affected by experiences; and behavioral epigenetic effects have been detected in mice (Murgatroyd et al., 2009), rhesus monkeys (Provençal et al., 2012), sheep (Sinclair et al., 2007), and human beings (McGowan et al., 2009), among other species. Thus, these sorts of epigenetic effects are likely the rule rather than the exception in complex animals. After considering the implications of this growing body of data, Weaver (2007) chose to subtitle a paper on the epigenetic effects of maternal behavior “Nature versus nurture: let’s call the whole thing off.”

The phenomena of behavioral epigenetics draw attention to the fact that behavior influences genetic activity, which influences behavior in a reciprocal manner, and so on. Thus, all phenotypes—adaptive and otherwise—emerge from epigenetic processes that are not predetermined by genetic factors, but are instead open to environmental/experiential inputs. As a result, it makes little sense to imagine that some behaviors can be explained strictly with reference to “phylogenetic contingencies” whereas others can be explained strictly with reference to “ontogenetic contingencies.” Obviously, the experiences we have while we develop can influence our subsequent behavior, even behavior exhibited many years after the experience; but it has now become clear that at least in some cases, experiences have their effects by influencing the activity of biological molecules that reflect evolutionary processes. So, as Lickliter (2009) has put it, “Whereas most accounts of development and evolution embraced by 20th-century biologists and psychologists focused on partitioning the organism’s phenotypic traits among those that are genetically determined and those that are produced by the environment, the remarkable findings now available from epigenetics demonstrate that no such partitioning is possible, even in principle” (p. 144). Instead, it now appears that nature and nurture can never be partitioned (Lickliter, 2009) or treated as independent contributors to development (Lewkowicz, 2011; Overton, 2006; Stotz, 2012). Furthermore, it now appears that DNA and non-genetic factors share causal parity (Griffiths & Tabery, 2013; Oyama, 1985), and therefore, that an organism’s phenotypes cannot be predicted prior to development simply by looking at that organism’s genome (Gottlieb, 1991a, 1992, 1998, 2007).

Conclusion: Why DS Proponents and Behavior Analysts Should be Natural Allies

There are good reasons to expect contemporary behavior analysts to find the DS approach to be congenial, and proponents of the DS approach should likewise be comfortable with most of the ideas that are essential to behavior analysis. One of the major objectives of those who have written in the DS tradition is to discourage references to instinctive or “genetically determined” behaviors, because such references effectively “black box” the mechanisms responsible for producing any so-labeled behaviors (Lehrman, 1953); speaking in this way permits the mistaken impression that genes can operate as agents able to independently cause behaviors. Rather than labeling behaviors in this obfuscating way, the DS approach insists on the importance of analysis of such behaviors, the goal being to elucidate the mechanisms by which proximate factors give rise to behaviors in real time. In the end, DS proponents are motivated by a desire to understand the provenance of behaviors, a goal that should feel quite familiar to behavior analysts.

Likewise, proponents of the DS approach maintain that context is always key. Behaviorists have traditionally recognized the important roles of contextual factors like discriminative stimuli, and proponents of the DS approach have consistently argued that contexts themselves must be recognized as an integral part of the system under study (Thelen & Smith, 1994). Similarly, like behavior analysts (e.g., Skinner, 1980), DS theorists believe that a thoroughgoing understanding of a given characteristic requires a historical analysis of the appearance of that characteristic. That is, knowing what an organism will do next is possible only if one is in possession of information about the organism’s previous states and experiences. Perhaps in part because advocates of the DS approach are concerned with both behavioral and other biological phenotypes, their focus on context is not limited to an organism’s context, but also includes the contexts of DNA, cells, organs, and other biological entities. Nonetheless, their acknowledgement of the critical importance of context remains consonant with fundamental principles of behavior analysis.

Just as behavior analysts should find themselves comfortable with the DS approach, proponents of the DS approach should be comfortable with the approach honed by behaviorists. After all, the consequences of behavior at one point in time normally contribute, as antecedent causes, to later behaviors. Therefore, one of the traditional concerns of some behaviorists—that is, the effects of the consequences of behavior (Schneider, 2012)—are also important to DS theorists, because some of these effects influence the mechanisms that cause subsequent behaviors. In fact, recent work in behavioral epigenetics, consistent with the DS approach, has uncovered ways in which learning has molecular effects in neurons, effects that alter the structure and functioning of the nervous system in ways that influence later behaviors (Day & Sweatt, 2010, 2011; Kandel, 2001; Levenson & Sweatt, 2005).

As Todd noted astutely in this journal in 1987, “behaviorism—as a philosophy of science—neither addresses specific empirical issues nor demands the use of a specific research methodology. Rather, it suggests that behavioral questions are best resolved by the analysis of behavior on its own level as the interaction of physical events…[the] traditional research interests and methodologies [of behaviorists] do not exhaust the possibilities of behaviorism” (p. 118). Accordingly, the behaviorist approach is fundamentally consistent with the DS approach, insofar as both are concerned with the analysis of behavior, and both recognize that such analysis requires study of interactions between physical entities. From this perspective, we should recognize the DS approach as a broad paradigm (Overton & Lerner, 2012) that can include behaviorism; traditional behaviorism does not look exactly like the DS approach merely because the “traditional research interests and methodologies” of behaviorists have remained more narrowly focused than their underlying philosophy of science permits. Ironically, the subtitle of Todd’s 1987 article—“Behaviorism’s presumed denial of instinct”—implied that behaviorists need not deny instinct even as the DS approach does just that; but when the content of Todd’s paper is considered with 29 years of hindsight, it continues to look as if DS theorists and behavior analysts should be natural allies.

One distinction between the DS approach and behavior analysis is that the former is concerned with the emergence of phenotypes in general rather than with behavior alone. Although many behavior analysts recognize that the category of “experience” encompasses more than learning, this point is particularly important to DS theorists, because the development of numerous phenotypes depends on non-genetic (i.e., experiential) factors other than learning. In these cases, experiences influence development in ways that influence phenotypes (including, sometimes, subsequent behavior) without necessarily producing the kinds of effects in a brain that would normally be associated with learning. For example, the physical effects of movement during embryonic development are known to influence features of tendons, ligaments, and bones in ways that have significant implications for behavior (Lickliter & Honeycutt, 2015). As Lickliter (2013) put it, DS theorists consider it “important to remember that experience is not synonymous with learning but rather refers much more broadly to function or activity, including the electrical activity of neurons, neurochemical and hormonal secretion, the use of muscles and sensory systems, and the behavior of the organism itself” (p. 84).

Some DS theorists have suggested that another difference between the approaches can be seen in their relative willingness to draw conclusions from ecologically unrealistic laboratory studies. Of course, ethologists working in the field have a long history of using the principles of behavior analysis to understand their observations, and there is a large literature that has demonstrated that operant principles can be generalized beyond the laboratory; everyone recognizes that ecological validity is important. But because the DS approach has been concerned for decades with questions about the relationship between development and evolution (Griffiths & Gray, 1994, 2005; Keller, 2005), DS proponents consider organism-environment systems to have co-evolved, and therefore, they expect organisms to respond differently in ecologically meaningful versus ecologically arbitrary testing contexts. Lickliter and Honeycutt 2013 (p. 186), for example, were concerned with this issue when they wrote the following:

Because organism–environment systems are tuned together over developmental and evolutionary time scales, we should expect special relationships between organisms and species-typical ecological events (Johnston, 1985). In much of traditional psychological analysis, however, subjects are placed in ecologically arbitrary situations and tested for responsiveness to ecologically arbitrary events. Such artificial, simplified studies may be necessary to isolate potential mechanisms of behavior, but such studies often overstate or understate how important certain factors are in real-life situations … [For example,] much of what we know about the acquisition of classically conditioned responses has been based on studies that involved conditioned stimuli that were ecologically arbitrary (e.g., pure tones or lights). However, when more ecologically realistic stimuli are used as conditioned stimuli in a variety of domains, the acquisition of conditioned responses are more rapid and resistant to extinction than when ecologically arbitrary (but still complex) stimuli are used (Domjan, 2005).

It can be helpful to remain aware of the different ways in which DS advocates and some behavior analysts think about “experience” in contrast to “learning,” and of their relatively different levels of tolerance for the use of ecologically valid experimental stimuli. Nonetheless, these differences do not render the two approaches at all incompatible.

Ultimately, the discovery that DNA is merely reactive to its context has strengthened developmentalists’ insistence that it is not helpful to consider any behaviors to be instinctive (Blumberg, 2005; Moore, 2002; Spencer et al., 2009). This insight means that careful analysis is required of the origins of all behaviors, origins that lie in the mechanical interactions that occur between biological entities and their contexts. The DS approach sees all phenotypes as being the product of developmental processes that utilize both genetic and non-genetic resources; consequently, the emergence of such traits can be understood only via developmental analysis. This means that efforts to find individual DNA segments that are responsible for particular behavioral conditions—for example, the search for “autism genes”—are doomed to failure. Instead, as behavior analysts and DS advocates agree, behaviors, including abnormal behaviors, must be understood to simultaneously reflect (1) an individual’s current environmental context, (2) the individual’s genetic state (i.e., the sequence of nucleotide bases in the DNA as well as the presence and state of numerous epigenetic factors that influence genetic expression), and (3) the individual’s developmental/experiential history (because that history has contributed to the structure and chemistry of the individual’s nervous system as well as to numerous other anatomical, physiological, and behavioral features of the individual). Clearly, the DS approach is an interdisciplinary one that seeks to illuminate phenotype origins by integrating the findings of several branches of biology (molecular, cellular, developmental, evolutionary); several branches of psychology (developmental, behavioral, psychobiological); and emerging disciplines (epigenetics, neuroscience); the goal is then to use the insights that are generated to elaborate mechanistic explanations of development (Lickliter, 2013). By synthesizing these numerous approaches to the study of behavior—including the approaches traditionally employed by behavior analysts—proponents of the DS approach seek to obtain comprehensive, generally applicable explanations regarding the origins of behavioral phenotypes. Such explanations will be useful if they can provide information about the likelihood that a given behavior will be observed in a given context, or if they can suggest ways to helpfully intervene in behavioral development.

Compliance with Ethical Standards

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Conflicts of interest

David S. Moore declares that he has no conflicts of interest.

Footnotes

1It is certainly reasonable to distinguish between categories of behavior based on other factors, such as whether or not the behavior is species-typical (for instance). The point here is that a comprehensive understanding of any behavior—however, it might be categorized in another scheme—requires a developmental analysis of its emergence.

References

  • Alberts, J. R., & Ronca, A. E. (2012). The experience of being born: a natural context for learning to suckle. International Journal of Pediatrics, 2012, Article ID 129328. doi: 10.1155/2012/129328. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  • Blumberg MS. Basic instinct: the genesis of behavior. New York: Thunder’s Mouth Press; 2005. [Google Scholar]
  • Borghol N, Suderman M, McArdle W, Racine A, Hallett M, Pembrey M, et al. Associations with early-life socio-economic position in adult DNA methylation. International Journal of Epidemiology. 2012;41:62–74. doi: 10.1093/ije/dyr147. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Burt CH, Simons RL. Pulling back the curtain on heritability studies: biosocial criminology in the postgenomic era. Criminology. 2014;52:223–262. doi: 10.1111/1745-9125.12036. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Chaufan C, Joseph J. The ‘missing heritability’ of common disorders: should health researchers care? International Journal of Health Services. 2013;43:281–303. doi: 10.2190/HS.43.2.f. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Cole SW, Hawkley LC, Arevalo JM, Sung CY, Rose RM, Cacioppo JT. Social regulation of gene expression in human leukocytes. Genome Biology. 2007;8:R189. doi: 10.1186/gb-2007-8-9-r189. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Day JJ, Sweatt JD. DNA methylation and memory formation. Nature Neuroscience. 2010;13:1319–1323. doi: 10.1038/nn.2666. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Day JJ, Sweatt JD. Epigenetic mechanisms in cognition. Neuron. 2011;70:813–829. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2011.05.019. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • DeCasper AJ, Fifer WP. Of human bonding: newborns prefer their mothers’ voices. Science. 1980;208:1174–1176. doi: 10.1126/science.7375928. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • DeCasper AJ, Spence MJ. Prenatal maternal speech influences newborns’ perception of speech sounds. Infant Behavior and Development. 1986;9:133–150. doi: 10.1016/0163-6383(86)90025-1. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Devlin AM, Brain U, Austin J, Oberlander TF. Prenatal exposure to maternal depressed mood and the MTHFR C677T variant affect SLC6A4 methylation in infants at birth. PLoS ONE. 2010;5(8):e12201. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0012201. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Ford DH, Lerner RM. Developmental systems theory: an integrative approach. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage; 1992. [Google Scholar]
  • Galton F. Inquiries into human faculty and its development. London/New York: J. M. Dent/E. P. Dutton (Originally published in 1883); 1907. [Google Scholar]
  • Gilbert SF. Synthesizing embryology and human genetics: paradigms regained. American Journal of Human Genetics. 1992;51:211–215. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • Gilbert SF, Sarkar S. Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century. Developmental Dynamics. 2000;219:1–9. doi: 10.1002/1097-0177(2000)9999:9999<::AID-DVDY1036>3.0.CO;2-A. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Godfrey-Smith P. On the status and explanatory structure of DST. In: Oyama S, Griffiths PE, Gray RD, editors. Cycles of contingency: developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 2001. pp. 283–297. [Google Scholar]
  • Goldstein MH, King AP, West MJ. Social interaction shapes babbling: testing parallels between birdsong and speech. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA. 2003;100:8030–8035. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1332441100. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Gomez-Pinilla F, Zhuang Y, Feng J, Ying Z, Fan G. Exercise impacts brain-derived neurotrophic factor plasticity by engaging mechanisms of epigenetic regulation. European Journal of Neuroscience. 2011;33:383–390. doi: 10.1111/j.1460-9568.2010.07508.x. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Gottlieb G. Experiential canalization of behavioral development: theory. Developmental Psychology. 1991;27:4–13. doi: 10.1037/0012-1649.27.1.4. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Gottlieb G. Experiential canalization of behavioral development: results. Developmental Psychology. 1991;27:35–39. doi: 10.1037/0012-1649.27.1.35. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Gottlieb G. Individual development and evolution: the genesis of novel behavior. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 1992. [Google Scholar]
  • Gottlieb G. Synthesizing nature-nurture: prenatal roots of instinctive behavior. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates; 1997. [Google Scholar]
  • Gottlieb G. Normally occurring environmental and behavioral influences on gene activity: from central dogma to probabilistic epigenesis. Psychological Review. 1998;105:792–802. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.105.4.792-802. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Gottlieb G. Probabilistic epigenesis. Developmental Science. 2007;10:1–11. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2007.00556.x. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Griffiths PE, Gray RD. Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. The Journal of Philosophy. 1994;91:277–304. doi: 10.2307/2940982. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Griffiths PE, Gray RD. Discussion: three ways to misunderstand developmental systems theory. Biology & Philosophy. 2005;20:417–425. doi: 10.1007/s10539-004-0758-1. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Griffiths PE, Stotz K. Genes in the postgenomic era. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics. 2006;27:499–521. doi: 10.1007/s11017-006-9020-y. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Griffiths PE, Tabery J. Behavioral genetics and development: historical and conceptual causes of controversy. New Ideas in Psychology. 2008;26:332–352. doi: 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.07.016. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Griffiths PE, Tabery J. Developmental systems theory: what does it explain, and how does it explain it? Advances in Child Development and Behavior. 2013;44:65–94. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-12-397947-6.00003-9. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Johnston TD. The persistence of dichotomies in the study of behavioral development. Developmental Review. 1987;7:149–182. doi: 10.1016/0273-2297(87)90011-6. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Johnston TD. Developmental systems theory. In: Blumberg MS, Freeman JH, Robinson SR, editors. Oxford handbook of developmental behavioral neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press; 2010. pp. 12–29. [Google Scholar]
  • Johnston TD, Gottlieb G. Neophenogenesis: a developmental theory of phenotypic evolution. Journal of Theoretical Biology. 1990;147:471–495. doi: 10.1016/S0022-5193(05)80260-7. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Johnston TD, Lickliter R. A developmental systems theory perspective on psychological change. In: Spencer JP, Thomas MSC, McClelland JL, editors. Toward a unified theory of development: connectionism and dynamic systems theory re-considered. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2009. pp. 285–296. [Google Scholar]
  • Joseph J. The trouble with twin studies: a reassessment of twin research in the social and behavioral sciences. New York: Routledge; 2015. [Google Scholar]
  • Kandel ER. The molecular biology of memory storage: a dialogue between genes and synapses. Science. 2001;294:1030–1038. doi: 10.1126/science.1067020. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Keller EF. DDS: dynamics of developmental systems. Biology & Philosophy. 2005;20:409–416. doi: 10.1007/s10539-004-1601-4. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Keller EF. From gene action to reactive genomes. Journal of Physiology. 2014;592:2423–2429. doi: 10.1113/jphysiol.2014.270991. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Kelso JAS. Principles of dynamic pattern formation and change for a science of human behavior. In: Bergman LR, Cairns RB, Nilsson L, Nystedt L, editors. Developmental science and the holistic approach. Mahwah, N.J.: Erlbaum; 2000. pp. 63–83. [Google Scholar]
  • Kuo ZY. The dynamics of behavior development: an epigenetic view. New York: Random House; 1967. [Google Scholar]
  • Lehrman DS. A critique of Konrad Lorenz’s theory of instinctive behavior. The Quarterly Review of Biology. 1953;28:337–363. doi: 10.1086/399858. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Lester BM, Tronick E, Nestler E, Abel T, Kosofsky B, Kuzawa CW, et al. Behavioral epigenetics. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 2011;1226:14–33. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2011.06037.x. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Levenson JM, Sweatt JD. Epigenetic mechanisms in memory formation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 2005;6:108–118. doi: 10.1038/nrn1604. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Lewkowicz DJ. The biological implausibility of the nature–nurture dichotomy and what it means for the study of infancy. Infancy. 2011;16:331–367. doi: 10.1111/j.1532-7078.2011.00079.x. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Lewontin RC. The triple helix: gene, organism, and environment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 2000. [Google Scholar]
  • Lickliter R. The fallacy of partitioning: epigenetics’ validation of the organism-environment system. Ecological Psychology. 2009;21:138–146. doi: 10.1080/10407410902877157. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Lickliter R. Biological development: theoretical approaches, techniques, and key findings. In: Zelazo PD, editor. Oxford handbook of developmental psychology. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. pp. 65–90. [Google Scholar]
  • Lickliter R, Berry TD. The phylogeny fallacy: developmental psychology’s misapplication of evolutionary theory. Developmental Review. 1990;10:348–364. doi: 10.1016/0273-2297(90)90019-Z. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Lickliter R, Honeycutt H. Biology, development, and human systems. In: Lerner RM, editor. Handbook of child psychology and developmental science. New York: John Wiley; 2015. pp. 162–207. [Google Scholar]
  • Lillycrop KA, Phillips ES, Jackson AA, Hanson MA, Burdge GC. Dietary protein restriction of pregnant rats induces and folic acid supplementation prevents epigenetic modification of hepatic gene expression in the offspring. Journal of Nutrition. 2005;135:1382–1386. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • Masataka N. Effects of experience with live insects on the development of fear of snakes in squirrel monkeys, Saimiri sciureus. Animal Behaviour. 1993;46:741–746. doi: 10.1006/anbe.1993.1251. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Maze I, Nestler EJ. The epigenetic landscape of addiction. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 2011;1216:99–113. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2010.05893.x. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • McGowan PO, Sasaki A, D’Alessio AC, Dymov S, Labonté B, Szyf M, et al. Epigenetic regulation of the glucocorticoid receptor in human brain associates with childhood abuse. Nature Neuroscience. 2009;12:342–348. doi: 10.1038/nn.2270. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Meaney MJ. Epigenetics and the biological definition of gene × environment interactions. Child Development. 2010;81:41–79. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2009.01381.x. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Meaney MJ, Szyf M. Maternal care as a model for experience-dependent chromatin plasticity? Trends in Neurosciences. 2005;28:456–463. doi: 10.1016/j.tins.2005.07.006. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Michel GF, Moore CL. Developmental psychobiology: an interdisciplinary science. Cambridge, MA: MIT; 1995. [Google Scholar]
  • Midgley BD, Morris EK. Nature = f(tnurture). A review of Oyama’s the ontogeny of information. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior. 1992;58:229–240. doi: 10.1901/jeab.1992.58-229. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. The dependent gene: the fallacy of nature vs. nurture. New York: W.H. Freeman; 2002. [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. A very little bit of knowledge: re-evaluating the meaning of the heritability of IQ. Human Development. 2006;49:347–353. doi: 10.1159/000096534. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. Individuals and populations: how biology’s theory and data have interfered with the integration of development and evolution. New Ideas in Psychology. 2008;26:370–386. doi: 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.07.009. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. Probing predispositions: the pragmatism of a process perspective. Child Development Perspectives. 2009;3:91–93. doi: 10.1111/j.1750-8606.2009.00083.x. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. Behavioral genetics, genetics, & epigenetics. In: Zelazo PD, editor. Oxford handbook of developmental psychology. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. pp. 91–128. [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. Current thinking about nature and nurture. In: Kampourakis K, editor. The philosophy of biology: a companion for educators. New York: Springer; 2013. pp. 629–652. [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. The asymmetrical bridge: book review of James Tabery’s “Beyond versus.” Acta Biotheoretica. 2015;63:413–427. doi: 10.1007/s10441-015-9270-z. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS. The developing genome: an introduction to behavioral epigenetics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2015. [Google Scholar]
  • Moore DS, Shenk D. The heritability fallacy [Individual development & behavior collection] WIREs Cognitive Science. 2016 [Google Scholar]
  • Morris EK, Lazo JF, Smith NG. Whether, when, and why Skinner published on biological participation in behavior. The Behavior Analyst. 2004;27:153–169. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • Murgatroyd C, Patchev AV, Wu Y, Micale V, Bockmühl Y, Fischer D, et al. Dynamic DNA methylation programs persistent adverse effects of early-life stress. Nature Neuroscience. 2009;12:1559–1566. doi: 10.1038/nn.2436. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Nijhout HF. Metaphors and the role of genes in development. BioEssays. 1990;12:441–446. doi: 10.1002/bies.950120908. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Noble D. The music of life: biology beyond genes. New York: Oxford University Press; 2006. [Google Scholar]
  • Overton WF. Developmental psychology: philosophy, concepts, methodology. In: Lerner R, editor. Handbook of child psychology. New York: John Wiley; 2006. pp. 18–88. [Google Scholar]
  • Overton WF, Lerner RM. Relational-developmental-systems: paradigm for developmental science in the postgenomic era. Brain and Behavioral Science. 2012;35:375–376. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12001082. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Oyama S. The ontogeny of information. Durham, NC: Duke University Press; 1985. [Google Scholar]
  • Oyama S, Griffiths PE, Gray RD. Cycles of contingency: developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 2001. [Google Scholar]
  • Plomin R, DeFries JC, McClearn GE, McGuffin P. Behavioral genetics. 5. New York: Worth; 2008. [Google Scholar]
  • Pradeu T. The organism in developmental systems theory. Biological Theory. 2010;5:216–222. doi: 10.1162/BIOT_a_00042. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Pradeu T. Toolbox murders: putting genes in their epigenetic and ecological contexts. Biology & Philosophy. 2015 [Google Scholar]
  • Provençal N, Suderman MJ, Guillemin C, Massart R, Ruggiero A, Wang D, et al. The signature of maternal rearing in the methylome in rhesus macaque prefrontal cortex and T cells. Journal of Neuroscience. 2012;32:15626–15642. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1470-12.2012. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Richardson K, Norgate SH. The equal environments assumption of classical twin studies may not hold. British Journal of Educational Psychology. 2005;75:339–350. doi: 10.1348/000709904X24690. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Roth TL, Lubin FD, Funk AJ, Sweatt JD. Lasting epigenetic influence of early-life adversity on the BDNF gene. Biological Psychiatry. 2009;65:760–769. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2008.11.028. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Schneider SM. Evolution, behavior principles, and developmental systems: a review of Gottlieb’s Synthesizing nature-nurture: prenatal roots of instinctive behavior. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior. 2003;79:137–152. doi: 10.1901/jeab.2003.79-137. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Schneider SM. The tangled tale of genes and environment: Moore’s The dependent gene: the fallacy of “nature vs. nurture.” The Behavior Analyst. 2007;30:91–105. [Google Scholar]
  • Schneider SM. The science of consequences: how they affect genes, change the brain, and impact our world. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books; 2012. [Google Scholar]
  • Schneirla TC. The concept of development in comparative psychology. In: Harris DB, editor. The concept of development: an issue in the study of human behavior. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press; 1957. pp. 78–108. [Google Scholar]
  • Shultziner D. Genes and politics: a new explanation and evaluation of twin study results and association studies in political science. Political Analysis. 2013;21:350–367. doi: 10.1093/pan/mps035. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Shultziner D. Fatal flaws in the twin study paradigm: a reply to Hatemi and Verhulst. Political Analysis. 2013;21:390–392. doi: 10.1093/pan/mpt008. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Sinclair KD, Allegrucci C, Singh R, Gardner DS, Sebastian S, Bispham J, et al. DNA methylation, insulin resistance, and blood pressure in offspring determined by maternal periconceptional B vitamin and methionine status. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA. 2007;104:19351–19356. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0707258104. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Skinner BF. In response: the species-specific behavior of ethologists. The Behavior Analyst. 1980;3:51. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • Spencer JP, Blumberg MS, McMurray B, Robinson SR, Samuelson LK, Tomblin JB. Short arms and talking eggs: why we should no longer abide the nativist–empiricist debate. Child Development Perspectives. 2009;3:79–87. doi: 10.1111/j.1750-8606.2009.00081.x. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Stewart I. Does god play dice? The mathematics of chaos. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell; 1989. [Google Scholar]
  • Stotz K. With ‘genes’ like that, who needs an environment? Postgenomics’s argument for the “ontogeny of information,” Philosophy of Science. 2006;73:905–917. doi: 10.1086/518748. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Stotz K. Murder on the development express: who killed nature/nurture? Biology & Philosophy. 2012;27:919–929. doi: 10.1007/s10539-012-9343-1. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Szyf M, Bick J. DNA methylation: a mechanism for embedding early life experiences in the genome. Child Development. 2013;84:49–57. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2012.01793.x. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Tabery J. Beyond versus: the struggle to understand the interaction of nature and nurture. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press; 2014. [Google Scholar]
  • Thelen E, Smith LB. A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 1994. [Google Scholar]
  • Todd JT. The great power of steady misrepresentation: behaviorism’s presumed denial of instinct. The Behavior Analyst. 1987;10:117–118. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • Van IJzendoorn MH, Bakermans-Kranenburg MJ, Ebstein RP. Methylation matters in child development: toward developmental behavioral epigenetics. Child Development Perspectives. 2011;5:305–310. doi: 10.1111/j.1750-8606.2011.00202.x. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Wallman J. A minimal visual restriction experiment: preventing chicks from seeing their feet affects later responses to mealworms. Developmental Psychobiology. 1979;12:391–397. doi: 10.1002/dev.420120413. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Weaver ICG. Epigenetic programming by maternal behavior and pharmacological intervention: nature versus nurture: let’s call the whole thing off. Epigenetics. 2007;2:22–28. doi: 10.4161/epi.2.1.3881. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Weaver ICG, Cervoni N, Champagne FA, D’Alessio AC, Sharma S, Seckl JR, et al. Epigenetic programming by maternal behavior. Nature Neuroscience. 2004;7:847–854. doi: 10.1038/nn1276. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Weaver ICG, Meaney MJ, Szyf M. Maternal care effects on the hippocampal transcriptome and anxiety-mediated behaviors in the offspring that are reversible in adulthood. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA. 2006;103:3480–3485. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0507526103. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Wereha TJ, Racine TP. Evolution, development, and human social cognition. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 2012;3:559–579. doi: 10.1007/s13164-012-0115-2. [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • West MJ, King AP. Settling nature and nurture into an ontogenetic niche. Developmental Psychobiology. 1987;20:549–562. doi: 10.1002/dev.420200508. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  • Witherington, D. C., & Lickliter, R. (2016). Integrating development and evolution in psychological science: evolutionary developmental psychology, developmental systems, and explanatory pluralism. Manuscript submitted for publication.
  • Zhang T-Y, Meaney MJ. Epigenetics and the environmental regulation of the genome and its function. Annual Review of Psychology. 2010;61:439–466. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.60.110707.163625. [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]


Articles from The Behavior Analyst are provided here courtesy of Association for Behavior Analysis International


Who argued that a scientific approach to development must focus only on observable behavior?

Watson began teaching psychology at Johns Hopkins University in 1908. In 1913, he gave a seminal lecture at Columbia University titled "Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It," which essentially detailed the behaviorist position. 1 According to Watson, psychology should be the science of observable behavior.

Which of the following is a similarity between Piaget's cognitive development theory and Vygotsky's sociocultural theory?

Which of the following is a similarity between Piaget's cognitive developmental theory and Vygotsky's sociocultural theory? ​Both see the child's functioning as adaptive.

Which of the following systems considers the influence of environmental changes that occur over time?

The fifth and final level of Bronfenbrenner's ecological systems theory is known as the chronosystem. This system consists of all of the environmental changes that occur over the lifetime which influence development, including major life transitions, and historical events.

What is a similarity between John Watson's Behaviourism and John Locke's concept of tabula rasa?

​ ​Both are types of stage theories. Which of the following is a similarity between John Watson's school of behaviorism and John Locke's concept of tabula rasa? Both suggest that experience determines one's ideas, preferences, and skills.